Tuesday, May 11, 2010

the X-MEN

SO.... I finally completed the download of the complete animated series of the X-Men last night. Very excited.
Does anyone else find it as interesting as me when your mystical childhood recollections are burst by revisiting something you once had a deep emotional attachment towards? It reminds me of the effects of a chemical we have when we are younger (can't remember the name of it)-- but it operates within our brain to make sensory experiences deeply intense when we are young. Ill have to do some research on that.

Anyway, the social philosophy of the X-Men is still quite relevant. In the first episode, Jubilee is sought out by a government agency that wishes to marginalize mutants (social deviants)/(insert your own marginalized group). Dr. Xavier is forced to see flaws in his blind optimism that though they are met with hostility by non-mutants, reason alone is not enough to break the hostile barrier into peace and co-existence.
As sort of a criticism to my own ideals, Magneto (in opposition to Xavier) views mutants as the next link in the chain of a superior human race (insert Nietzsche's Ubermench). It is the expression of the superior mutant force that should reign and direct the future evolution of the human species. [Bridge my ideals here with vulnerability.... ]

Xavier goes into the mental barriers of Sabretooth in episode 3. The animation is quite a bit outdated, but the concept of Xavier fighting with Sabretooth, inside his mind, against the monstrous subjects and manifestations of his personal emotional barriers to an enlightened understanding of himself and the world is still socially relevant. It is so amazing to see how the real, layered meaning of this series can go lost on a child but still hold a powerful sway over them, only to lose some of its luster in its rediscovery as an adult EVEN in light of now grasping its total and very relevant meanings.

I guess I just cant get past a lot of the cheese-ball lines and unimpressive animated effects given the technological progress we have made since 1988-1993. We can demonstrate so much more with technology in and of concepts nowadays with just the impartation of images, and their organization. I ripped Iron Man 2 a couple nights ago as it got released in Russia apparently. The development of even our movie special effects seems to bring the realization to us that our science is not that far off. You'll see what I am talking about if you go see the movie and observe what kind of an office Robert Downey Jr.'s character has to operate with. Science fiction has its way of speaking/writing technological advancements into our dreams and therefore into existence.

Aaaaand..... with that this may be my last blog. Time is coming to a close, and I am out of steam. I have been pressing so hard these last days that I just want to relax for a bit and enjoy the peaceful, stress-less reflection of a semester that still has more to teach me as I continue to remember it.

I have loved this blogging thing.... and I will definitely read all the writings of the class that I haven't gotten to yet and post comments as I am inspired. I'll probably even keep posting a thing here and there even though the grading is over.

It has been nice to know all of you, as the class room and library has allowed, and am only sorry my busyness hasn't allowed me to invest into your personal thoughts and lives more as I had hoped and planned at the beginning of the semester.

Maybe in the future...

~Sterling

Ayer's Logical Positivism

I know we are all in the common study of the History of Classical Philosophy, and the classical thought we deal with doesn't really get too deep into Empiricism (beyond its predecessors in the Atomists/Elementalists), but reading Ayer and Russell on the side this semester has been difficult for me. And so, in that struggle, I have tried to clarify (to myself) what I can glean from the meaning of these two and form some conclusions of my own, because much of my direction in philosophical study has its foundation, and relies, on what we can empirically know.

If you have read my other blogs you know that I have metaphysical, normative understandings of the universe that would already imply that I reject much of what the logical positivist has to offer.

In any event... This is my treatment of what I understand of Ayer's logical positivism. I'll be taking a class with Dr. Marcum this summer where I hope he illuminates my understanding here a bit.


Dr. Baird briefly touched on the Logical Positivists this semester (and it is because of his mention of them that I looked into it)-- So, I'll begin with how he characterized their movement:

~One thesis and One fundamental Claim: All cognitively meaningful propositions are either analytic or empirically verifiable

Analytic statements such as those in math/logic/language are empirical: OR, they are Nonsense

Metaphysical statements are pseudo-statements and are not cognitively meaningful

Just so happens, though that the thesis: All cognitively meaningful propositions are either analytic, empirically verifiable, or they are non-sense Is neither analytic nor empirically verifiable.

So... onto Ayer:

1... For Ayer, truth is first defined as being meaningful. Ayer requires that which is meaningful to be relevant to the world as it can be experienced; what could possibly be meaningful if it is impossible to experience? Once one agrees that truth could not be truth unless it is perceived to be so, then it is only logical to exclude all other persuasions from its serious pursuit. This being Ayer’s foundation, inherited from Russell and Hume, he must reject metaphysics and all other propositions which can be neither proven true nor false by “some possible sense-experience.” Ayer doesn’t attack the fruit of the metaphysician’s field, rather he argues that it is impossible for a metaphysician to make any sense at all seeing as the sentences they use, or propositions to be more accurate, cannot meet a significant definition of such, as they have no experiential meaning and thus no means to be proven true or false. For Ayer, such propositions are “literally senseless.” Ayer wants to argue, now that he has corrected the past problems of philosophers, that the philosopher’s job is never to conflict with the hypotheses of science and is to champion the refinement of logic as it can be used to sharpen the propositions of scientists. Philosophers and their philosophies are warned of inevitable frivolity by Ayer if they do not liken to their only useful role as that of scientists of logic.

2... The original verification principal only required that in order to determine whether or not a sentence had “literal meaning,” the proposition it expressed must be either analytically or empirically verifiable. Ayer dances in rebuttal to his critics as he offers one hedge after another. Ayer admits that a given sentence, even one he would say is meaningless, inherently implies an expression. To this possible “meaning” of a sentence, Ayer introduces the equivocation of the terms: sentence and proposition so that he may substitute the word “statement” synonymously for “sentence” while reserving the word “proposition” to continue to refer to the expressions of statements which can be either empirically or analytically verified. However, the full apologetic move arrives when the very word “verifiable” wants definition. Weak and strong verifiability are introduced so that the author does not find himself in a trap where he must categorize all that which the scientific method has yet to verify as meaningless. Offering this hedge of weak verification allows Ayer to escape a logical black hole of contradiction by allowing a degree of meaning to phenomena which could be conceivably verifiable by experience. In the end, it seems as though the stress of the author’s own defense has him parting with logic where he backs his own right to make uncertain assumptions in the face of an always present uncertainty which therefore must be assigned a probability factor according to some derived potentiality of experience.

Brief Break from the Blogging Sweat Shop; On Tradition and Birthdays

So.... Yesterday was my birthday, yes, as some of you friends in class and "Facebookers" have noticed. I wanted to take the time here and thank you all for the wonderful birthday wishes. I have more to complete in this class, or I would be enjoying my family's Crawfish Boil right now with a bloody marry in hand. :))

Admonishment to you 21's and younger: The glory and celebration surrounding your birthday sharply fades at the 22nd birthday. No one tells you that this is going to happen....it just does.

Philosophically, birthdays are funny to me. Like Christmas. A birthday really is nothing more than the annual acknowledgment of the day that you were thrown into this world and that you happen to still be in this world. We have made much more cultural add-ons to the event, seemingly to make it also a celebration of wanting to make that person feel good, to affirm to them the reasons that we like them, or to make them puke and drool on themselves for our own amusement. Like, Christmas.... well, in my family at least :). The convention of Christmas has its pagan roots and arbitrary date, and weird, disconnected conventions that seem to do nothing with-- if you would ask a Christian-- its organic intention.

All in all, it is just peculiar how grown up traditions start to replace our intent...generation after generation, and that we allow this in-authentic practice for ourselves even with half and full awareness of it.

"Every tradition now grows more venerable the farther away its origin lies and the more this origin is forgotten; the respect paid to it increases from generation to generation, the tradition at last becomes holy and evokes awe and reverence; and thus the morality of piety is in any event a much older morality than that which demands unegoistic acts."
Nietzsche, "Human, All Too Human"

Monday, May 10, 2010

Phaedo; Against Plato's Recollection of the Forms; a work in progress

The theory of recollection that Plato puts forth in Phaedo and Meno hinges on the supposition that all non-empirical “knowledge” is recalled from a communion with the Forms prior to birth; his theory stands myopic and venerable to the copious alterative possibilities for coming about such “knowledge.” Once it is seen that Plato’s Forms aren’t the contingent conclusion of the intuitive “reason” to which his character Simmias conveniently stipulates, it becomes clear that Plato’s subsequent epistemologies and proofs for God (and the immortal soul) are rendered unsound, if not invalid.

Wanting to be fair and charitable to Plato’s approach to “pre-epistemology”, it is important to establish his definition of knowledge. Plato makes two distinctions of knowledge. First, it could be said that Plato understands that there is an encounter with experience which is composed of events and facts which one observes once one is born. To know that Barrack Obama is the current president of the United States is an empirical fact which Plato will deemphasize in his epistemology if he can’t totally it reject as knowledge. Though Descartes will come later, and it can’t been argued that Plato has avoided the possibility of doubting even these “facts” as a certainty of life in the context of an Evil Deceiver, he at least permits it as an observation irrelevant to his own definition of knowledge. The types of knowledge which Plato chooses to say are valid are the concepts (such as equality, justice, et cetera) of which there appears to be no other way of knowing without it existing before the individual became aware of it. Here, Plato’s argument is that, referring to equality, it must exist in some perfect Form in order for our understanding of it to be possible since it is clear that it is inherently unavoidable to escape making such distinctions as part of human nature.

Whenever someone, on seeing something, realizes that that which he now sees wants to be like some other reality but falls short and cannot be like that other since it is inferior, do we agree that the one who thinks this must have prior knowledge of that which he says it is like?…this is possible only if our soul existed before it took on this human shape (Phaedo, 74e, 72e respectively).

This argument has also planted the seeds for later work such as St. Anselm’s powerful ontological argument which blooms into the conclusion, in short, that because one cannot dispute that he can conceive of a supreme being; a supreme being must exist. Though Plato does not go this route, his contention agrees that to conceive of a transcendent Form beyond our natural world, is to inherently necessitate its existence, and that by making the observation that as things in this world bear resemblance to such abstract notions as equality, is to prove that all knowledge of these things is a function of recalling them from an a priori communion with their Form.

Plato desires to use his theory of recollection as the proof which solidifies the existence of Forms and consequentially implies an immortal, transcendent nature of the soul even if nothing can be concluded about the nature of the longevity of the soul. In light of the originally mentioned vulnerabilities of such thinking, it seems sophomoric to say that the most important criticisms here are that Plato fails to answer how it is that the soul originally exists in order to relate to such Forms. And it is additionally superficial to find it constructive to say that this philosophy fails where Plato doesn’t propose a complete system for understanding how and why something in this world could and should embody an inferior Form of itself. These points are ancillary chidings which only allude to the incomprehensible nature of our complex existence which ends up giving the philosophy more credit than it deserves.

Beyond Plato’s validly suspicious assumption that the origin of knowledge must come through a recollection of a prior relationship to transcendent Forms, these thoughts are very interesting and should be taken seriously but only in the context that it is one of many possibilities rather than a freestanding proof. It is the other more plausible and even the exceedingly mystical alternatives of modern epistemology which throw Plato’s contention of proof into the quagmire of competing theory. One diametrically opposed view to this epistemology, but with many salient tenants, is that of modern existentialist Michel Foucault. Foucault argues that every human being, without being able to control it, enters into an existence without any fixed point of reference other than the current cultural context. And that, though time, history shows that all that has been done in the name of reaching a more enlightened understanding of the knowledge of human nature has been a regurgitation and reinvention of the same application of ideas and terms which were borrowed from some other point in history. Foucault, though having many problems with this view as well, has just as validly replaced Plato’s need for transcendence with an ignorant adaptation of history’s terms, definitions and values. Just for means of comparison, Foucault wishes to remove the individual from the marginalizing effects of such assumed and inherited ideas of knowledge by emphasizing the importance of the individual to create an original perspective concerning the nature of concepts so that it is the human cause that is progressed rather than the stagnation that has resulted in the preoccupation of generations to cling to enshrined ideas purported by past philosophers who claimed to have the proofs concerning the truth of what we know and how to go about knowing it. And briefly, another, though more fanciful idea about how we come to know things, is the theory of collective consciousness. Collective consciousness is an idea that wildly, but plausibly, adapts Leibniz’s metaphysics (that all of existence is connected by spiritual/biological cells called monads) and that these monads complexly react to each other throughout all that are so composed, linking every brain in some degree or another. Through this philosophy, it is believed that all of our knowledge is really shared (arguably in complex energy packets called photons receivable by the monad) subconsciously, eternally and continuously in relation with the ultimate monad called Lambda. Wild and unconventional as this latter philosophy may seem, it shares many obvious parallels and defining distinctions with Plato’s conjectures, and yet is just as plausible as the theory of recollection (especially if one invites the findings of the theoretical possibility of such waves and their receipt).

You may think that Plato’s was right, or it may be the case that our seemingly inherent sense of concepts are only a complex, naturalistic manifestation and evolution of the human brain. What is clear, however, is that it is human nature to be curious about the relationship of concepts to our existence and to discover the different implications along the way, but to date there is no proof, and humanity does not have to bear Plato’s mark as brilliant an option as it is. I see no need for conclusion here, actually. On a matter as important as this I think it is alright to treat certainty as an illusion.

Foucault

What is Continental Philosophy? Can anyone give me an exhaustive understanding of this branch of philosophy?

As finals, and the semester, come to a close I plan on reading as much Continental Philosophy as I can. Shayan and Ray... I know you both have read a fair amount in this area and would appreciate yours and everyone else's suggestions.

Here and there I have been building notes and an outline concerning Michel Foucault and his works (pirmarily Madness and Civilization, since I haven't exhausted the work and am hesitant to move on until I do). It is sort of a hobby and I would like to share some of this and invite thoughts about my representation of Foucault and his ideas.

Foucault Bio:

Foucault was born in Poitiers, France, on June 15, 1926.

Foucault became academically established in the 1960’s and went on to hold numerous and varied positions in top French Universities (also to include a stint at UC Berkeley in 1983) before he finished out his career as the Professor of the History of Systems of Thought at the College de France, this latter position is still considered one of the highest academic positions in French education. Primarily concerned with the histories and related impacts of medicine and social sciences, Foucault’s passions lead him to protest on behalf of homosexuals and other groups he felt were marginalized in society. Foucault died in Paris on June 25th, 1984 due to complications of the AIDS virus.

Foucault’s Most Notable Works:

“Madness and Civilization” (1961)

“The Order of Things” (1966)

“The Order of Discourse” (1971)

“The History of Sexuality” published in three volumes:

Vol. I: An Introduction [1976]

Vol. II: The Use of Pleasure [1984]

Vol. III: The Care of the Self [1984]

“Aesthetics, Method and Epistemology” (1998)

“Power” (2000)

Timeline of Madness:

~The Medieval Period: leprosy fades in prevalence and madness assumes its station in society. Madness is seen as having a dark connection with (if not inspired by) the divine. Society’s attitude toward madness in this period is marked by a curious admiration.

~The Renaissance: The 17th Century’s full integration of madness into society; art and literature give it a voice.

FOCUS: Classical Period: 1660-19th Century

    ~Foucault sees this period as giving birth to many of the lasting states of our modernity.

    ~Period of “Confinement” dawns with the building of the Hospital General in 1656 and with a cultural shift in practice and attitude towards madness. Madness shifts from a tolerated part of society to a threat to society’s organization, safety and progress. Society changes its identity as a result of its relation to madness.

    Terms relative to Foucault’s interpretation of the Classical Period:

      “Confinement:” practice, specific to the 18th century, whereby society creates a space for social deviants to be locked up, silenced and excluded from society. Included in the list of “deviants” were: criminals, the unproductive poor and the perceived mad. Confinement, like many of Foucault’s categories and definitions, is better understood as a condition of society’s attitude toward deviance and madness rather than a physical condition of bondage or natural phenomenon. The Hospital General became a physical representation of the contrast of society’s shift in attitudes between the 17th century’s integration of madness and “unreason,” and the 18th century’s desire to exclude and silence it.

      “Madness:” is essentially defined by Foucault as being within the construction and control of the intellectual and cultural forces which operate within society. The treatment of the mad depends fundamentally on how they are perceived. Therefore madness is not a fixed concept which natural phenomena can explain. Madness is always defined against society’s current attitudes and ideas about reason and rationality. In the middle ages, madness was associated with dark secrets and visions of the end of the world; in the classical period it was confined along with other forms of social deviance and lost its “exclusive status.” The modern idea of madness as a treatable mental disease developed from nineteenth century ideas of madness as a kind of moral evil.

      “Unreason:” has somewhat of a relationship to madness in that it, too, is a non-static term defined in relation to reason. Foucault calls “unreason” reason “dazzled”. It seems that he means to say that “reason dazzled” is an alternative perspective of experience and reality which can be a symptom of madness or can also be completely distinct from it.

      “Delirium:” the general move away from reason (by whatever cause) and made sustainable by a “discourse.”

      “Discourse:” central to most of Foucault’s work: a totaled system of knowledge which makes certain statements either true or false. Ex: A madman’s discourse is “especially powerful” citing that it consistently allows the subject’s deviance to be sustained.

      “Police:” defined by Foucault as dealing with an ideological set of practices meant to facilitate work and to protect the interests of work and the “order” it provides society. Work as being inherently “good” rose primarily as a Christian theme. Madmen and the practitioners of unreason consistently contrast to this idea of society.

    ~Role of the Passions:

    The possibility of madness is therefore implicit in the very phenomenon of passion.”

    ~M. Foucault, “Madness and Civilization”

    ***(Cartesian link between mind and body (soul and body), thus allowing madness???)

~19th Century: Characterized by the end of “classical confinement” and an additional shift in attitude toward madness, making it a condition of moral evil and “treatable” in asylums by the employment of religiously influenced power relationships between doctor and patient.

Source Voices of Foucault’s madmen: King Lear, Artaud, Nietzsche and more…

Since the end of the nineteenth century, unreason no longer manifests itself except in the lightning flash of works such as those of Hoederlin, of Nerval, of Nietzsche, or of Artaud.”

~Foucault, “Madness and Civilization”

Foucault’s Conclusions about Madness and Civilization:

Foucault claims that we don’t listen to the voice of the madman, that psychoanalysis and all other forms of “treatment” used under the guise of a positive “confinement” are a façade and a symptom of how we are bound to the paradigms of a particular era.

Foucault sees the relationship of art to madness as being the only avenue through which “unreason” and “madness” can surface to be understood and appreciated even considering the efforts of the aforementioned medical structures to hide it. Foucault also claims that art attempts to “fight against the world” and to reconcile the balance between madness and society by “asking the world disturbing questions and requiring answers.” This provides a stark contrast to the solution proposed by modern psychiatrists and psychologists who impose a perspective of moral judgment onto their captive subjects. Madness exists in the undercurrent of society in the works of mad authors and should be considered in such light to find relevance rather than to have it marginalized.

Implications for a Critique of Historical Reason: ??

With this perspective involving the historical analysis of the reason of society, Foucault hijacks the project of modern epistemology from the hands of Kant.


:::::::ITEMS TO EXPAND:::::


Form a chart from: Descartes to Foucault Does

Foucault stand Kant on his head??

General Controversy & Critique:

Historical Inaccuracy: The Ship of Fools?

Preferential sampling: artists & their interesting products are Foucault’s focus

~the mundane “madman” seems uninteresting to Foucault

~calls into question the universality of Foucault’s picture of the madman

Gen. Note~Foucault’s sentence structure can be very cloudy and unclear: intended to let the reader experience the “discourse” of the madman? or simply an inability to write clearly due to an affinity for obscurity?

Brings to mind Nietzsche:

"Whoever knows he is deep, strives for clarity; whoever would like to appear deep to the crowd, strives for obscurity. For the crowd considers anything deep if only it cannot see to the bottom: the crowd is so timid and afraid of going into the water."

~Nietzsche....aphorisms, source???

BIO POWER:

“Bio-Power” becomes Foucault’s ultimate existential conclusion which attempts to synthesize all his works. Through the synthesis all of his work, Foucault wants us to see that what and who you think you are in your heart as person and as people in a society is nothing more than an evolution of contingent historical factors. He sees the incorporation of the individual’s needs for passion, comfort and accomplishment into the state, as an empowering affirmation of life. This is the potential “bio-power” that modern politics posses to emerge from judgments and repression of the individual, into an era which transcends the chain of historical contingency.

In Support of MLK's Love of Enemies

We started off our class with King's Letter from Birmingham Jail, and I though I love King's rhetoric, I think it mostly serves to subtly warp his logic into emotive force for his point. Plato would have a problem here with King if he were to view, as I do, that King's dabbles in Sophistry from time to time and- even being a philosophy major- he tends to handicap his fierce logical mind with a pre-occupation with a particular locality of interest.
However, I recently read a speech that King gave about loving your enemies and I greatly agree with his intuitive insights.
Here, I treat King unto himself. In a later blog I will want to compare Aristotle and King in this area of loving your enemies.

King delves into his process for “loving thy enemy” as prescribed by Christ in the Book of Matthew. His method starts with self evaluation citing that loving an enemy is intrinsically related to self analysis. This is the type of self analysis that is introspectively aware, delicately yoked and honest enough to admit that it may be responsible for the very actions that have incited the contempt of an enemy. Starting from this vantage, it is easy to see where King is moving with this and how his model of “love” has global implications especially in context of the tumultuous political and social conditions of his era. King’s next step is to contend that it is inherent to contain goodness being created in the image of God, and that to overcome the obvious hurdles involved with loving an enemy, the individual must seek and dwell upon whatever shard of goodness lies within the enemy as it is “within the best of us, there is some evil, and within the worst of us, there is some good”. Now, essentially, we are to put this love into practice by proving our heartfelt understanding of “goodwill for all men” by “refusing to defeat any individual” when the opportunity presents itself. This has a parallel in the modern, mainstream religious maxim: “love the sinner, hate the sin.” For King, this is accomplished though his highest form of love: “love of others for God’s sake”, which he borrowed from Plato and “Bernard of Clavicaux.” Though it is agreeable that this is a plausible plan for transforming perspective into humanistic love, the problem of its obvious lack of modern application lies within the tendency to be abstract and paradoxically objectifying of the actual individual. When the individual is loved for the sake of something else, it is causal that the individual is not loved for his reasons alone. Most anything becomes lovable in the abstract where an idea of the person is conjured to take the place of his existential qualities. Though King’s system requires much adherence, the objectifying and abstraction of love for people stands as an obvious impediment to its universal presence today. King does not stop here. The impact that hate has on the “hater” is described by King as to turn inside out the very perspective and values of the individual. And it makes experiential sense that a preoccupation with things that an individual hates is really more telling of that individual than it is of those things. King contends in his speech that even what was ugly to the person turns beautiful and what was hailed as bad becomes the good. Conversely, it appears true that love has the power to build individuals. This provides sounds experiential reason for finding ways to avoid hate and to love your enemy. The anecdote posited by King referring to Abraham Lincoln seems to embody King’s philosophy of love here while cleverly (though it may not have been his intention) turning the popular phrase “keep your friends close and your enemies closer” into a fanciful oxymoron.

Freud and Nietzsche: Where's the Vulnerability?...that other 1/2 of our Nature?

Where Nietzsche sees the perversion of the authentic human instinct to express its will as occurring at the moment where individuals subjugated their autonomous powers in the form of contracts with each other, the psychological insights of Sigmund Freud become relevant. In Future of an Illusion, Freud sites that such a contract between individuals would constitute a society and that all societies are “built up on coercion and renunciation of instinct.” As implied by Nietzsche, and made explicit by Freud, societies, by their very definition, force their constituents to renounce their instinctual drives by subjugating personal autonomy to an external will. Freud’s psychoanalysis contends that the act of subjugation by society is accomplished through a “prohibition,” which is a regulation that disallows the “satisfaction of an instinct.” When an instinct is not allow to be satisfied, it “frustrates” the individual leading to conditions of “privation” which are internalized as “kernels of hostility toward civilization.” Though Nietzsche’s polemic devices are intended to warn humanity that it risks sterilizing its own will to power, thus providing for its own extinction, he can also be seen as agreeing with Freud in that, underneath the centuries of synthetic moral practice, the future health of humanity depends on the ability for a generation of human animals to “conquer God” through the work of the same psychological devices that subjected us to him. Freud and Nietzsche essentially want the same thing. Freud, too, would like to free humanity from its slave-like adherence to religious morality by absolving the human psyche in the realization that religion, and god, are psychological illusions.

Some Frustrations with Hume

As the semester closes, I find myself making a summary of several Philosophers. And it has been with Kant and Hume, (even though I largely agree with Hume's empiricism)-- that I find my objections standing out most. Specifically in reference to the beginning chapters of Hume's "An Enquiry Concerning the Principals of Morals:"

Hume begins, on page 73, with a forceful ad hominem directed at those who do not share in his idea that there are such things as moral distinctions. Plainly, why must it be a “blind adherence” to some supposed (straw-man) myopic dedication that is the only option out of Hume’s depiction of morals as being discernable through reason and made effectual by sentiment? Hume will say on page 74: “Truth is discernable; not taste.” He seems to allow the first part of this causal to stand for the logical faculties present in reason for the discovery of truths (presumably the ‘truth’ that there are indeed such things as morals). Here it is as though Hume has said that because there is reason there are morals. In rushing so far ahead of himself with his supposed powers of reason (reason is also somehow attributed, without reason, with the “standard of our judgment”), Hume has only managed to stipulate the inherited ideas of moral (from ancient philosophers, etc) by performing no rational deconstruction of the nature of the term “moral.”

Hume moves on in his unexamined assumptions to assert that the reason for “moral [speculation] is to teach us our duty.” The function of this speculation serves to mold the “habits” of humans to want an association with virtue and an avoidance of vice. Here, Hume says that reason is not sufficient to mold human behavior if sentiment does not make one feel compelled to move into certain, assumed and favorable speculations of morals. This is where Hume finds his marriage between reason and sentiment. Reason to discover (or, produce as he gives no definitions prohibiting this equation of terms) morality and sentiment to make it compelling when reason produces “indifferent” truths.

This may be a fine mechanistic/empirical depiction of how morality is produced in a state where duty-to-conform holds a value even higher than the constructs of morality which were made for it, but where is the truth Hume promised concerning reaching “the foundation of ethics.” It is not foundational to say that we will strive hard to get to the bottom of what morals are by assuming some version of their popular/inherited constructs and mechanisms. Foundational to the discussion of this topic would look something like Nietzsche’s etymology, where he posits that the very term “moral” has been added to and elevated, over time, through effort and sacrifice to produce an unnecessarily complexed term, which is purely synthetic and no longer represents anything authentic about human nature. Even if Nietzsche’s critique is found to be flawed and not conducive to the edification of a community as it is wanted to exist, Hume promised to “consider every aspect of the [human] mind” for these fundamental answers, and instead he only floats on a surface analysis of popular moral application and function.

Some Frustrations with Kant

Given the mental effort Kant expends on the separation of rationality into one (pure speculative reason) that can only relate to the formal, and the other, it’s fraternal twin (pure practical reason), which is limited to the anthropological, or material— We can see Kant is engaging in the redefinition of human reason by compounded abstraction so as to allow for the validity of his opening thesis: “It is impossible to think of anything at all in the world, or indeed even beyond it, that could be considered good without limitation except a good will.” Reason, in these two parts, is then conflated by Kant and is said to have the ability (and almost an insinuated teleological purpose) for somehow shaping the human “will” into something that cannot be exceeded in its resultant moral worth. Here, Kant’s assumptions alone place reason in this capacity, imbuing it with strange metaphysical powers which can somehow make other abstract concepts (i.e. the “will”) contain an infinite amount of yet other abstract terms (“good”) so that this mental concept of “will,” now confounded by abstraction upon abstraction, is made, as a purely artificial construct, to reveal itself to the constituents of the empirical domain as being that thing of the greatest possible worth for them. It is only within the border of Kant’s abstract playground that ideas can be fantasized into containing infinity of anything. As soon as an “unlimited” notion of “good” crosses the empirical threshold, it must shed all infinity that was metaphysically attributed to it. So, in our finite actuality, no thing can be “good in itself.” “Good in itself,” is a purely rational concept and may be postulated and played with in the playground of the mind, but it will always remain a potentiality within this mind as the term is held together by circular reasoning, is defined entirely by abstractions and is fashioned together by Coherentism.

When it comes to the moment for Kant to offer a convincing, fundamental truth (whether through the critique of a pure practical reason, or that of a pure speculative reason; we would not begrudge Kant his own tools) about how we might come to see, or even want, ourselves as necessarily linked to his subjugating duty-action theory of morality, Kant honestly replies that he cannot “see what [his] respect” for the Universal Law “is based upon.” It may be that he cannot see the principal which animates respect because he has forgotten that, for it to be intelligible within the constructs of his normative system, he must first, and separately, construct its value and meaning in the abstract chamber so that its definition and function end up being precisely tailored per what is needed for the Categorical Imperative to gain increased favor over the human being. For Kant, the subjugation of humanity to a “pure” moral philosophy is obviously preferred over efforts made in search of the fundamental truths about morality.

Science and Identity; I am in Want of a Functionalist's Mechanism

This will be a slight detour into the value of Scientists in our contemporary search for a unified vision. It may be arguable to some that the most meaningful task of the contemporary Philosopher is to find some avenue into reconciling our human identity with the material world. Dr. Baird has quoted the following to death all semester, but the intense relevance and action-shaping power of the quote to follow never looses its grasp on my beginning into every thought and every action.

“The most important question in contemporary philosophy is this: How, and to what extend, can we reconcile a certain conception that we have of ourselves as conscious, mindful, free, social and political agents with a world that consists entirely of mindless, meaningless particles in fields of force? How, and to what extent, can we get a coherent account of the totality of the world that will reconcile what we believe about ourselves with what we know for a fact from physics, chemistry and biology?” (Searle, Freedom & Neurobiology, 26)


I will not be able to say anything more poignant than that, and I will not attempt my own reconciliation though I have thoughts on how we may try this. I will keep my thoughts general and get into the particulars later if time allows...and maybe even if it doesn't.

We can only stand on the shoulders of giants . . . Giants who loved their work knowing that for as long as there are questions their work remains open. The history of science is littered with love-tortured souls whose furious dedication to the minute was fueled by the idea that this life may not live to see the synthesis of the most pertinent questions. So from one Giant's truth, to the page, to your eyes, from your lips? If words truly build understandings within you, it would be your experience to which those words attach-- it would be the truest thing you have lived that came pouring from you. You wouldn't be able to help this. We are always telling others what we don't know when we are saying the things we think we know. When we have lived, it is our lives that illuminate, ask questions of and wrestle with a reading, a new person, new philosophical perspective. But only when added to education can our minds build crucial understandings out of phenomena whose only promise is to remain suspended in the abstract.

There will always be new information. And there are no such things as "hypocrites" except for those who use the word to indicate that they wish to stay as they are. In our common tongue, we use the word hypocrite as nothing more than a condemnation of one who subscribes to a particular system, which we have inherited and have been conditioned to find palatable, in the hopes that we may shame them from any and all deviance that, as copies, might make us feel inadequate by relation. Both stability and ignorance are sustained by this informal constraint so popularly employed.

An Agnostic's Application of a Bible Passage, Or "Noted While Reading"


first chapter of proverbs starting with verse 19

"So are the ways of everyone that is greedy of gain; which taketh away the life of the owners thereof...How long , ye simple ones, will ye love simplicity? and the scorners delight in their scorning and fools hate knowledge? Turn you at my reproof; behold, I will pour out my spirit unto you, I will make known my words unto you.
Because I have called, and ye refused; I have streatched out my hand, and no man regarded;
But ye have set at nought all my counsel, and would none of my reproof...
When your fear cometh as desolation, and your destruction cometh as a whirlwind; when distress and anguish cometh upon you. Then shall they call upon me, but I will not answer; They shall seek me early, but they shall not find me:
For they that hated knowledge, and did not choose the fear of the Lord;
They would none of my counsel: they despised all my reproof.
Therefore they shall eat of the fruit of their own way, and be filled with their own devices."

Noted while reading:
What struck me here is that it seems especially tragic, and poignantly bleak for our country's future, to find so many pursuers of "higher education" mired in a paradigm that confounds "greedy gain" with lifelong habits of self justification. Choreographed conversations that dance to gimmicky tunes characteristic of power plays and "who's who" gossip, these leverage games are symptomatic of a bed-ridden people, a people made so sick by the putrid cloud of inherited ideas, that most will never see that their lives were spent lying down boasting of bedsores. And what sort of contribution is this?
This is not to discount the value of ambitious people hungry to put good information to better uses . . . I am one such person. It just so happnes that "Lovers of simplicity" and the haters of Knowledge are made so by a betrayal of their own ambitions. Ambition and good intention have always been tools available to the inept and confused in order to make very large messes. Their tradegy is one of details: Their greed is a love of systems, their useful information is pulled from synthetic ideas-- shadows on the wall of a cave-- and their hatred is for you and me. We are the living Knowledge, a fleshy counterpoint to technological convieniance, the foil of every carefully constructed appearance; we are what they passionately construct out of surrogate materials having wrestled the reality from none of us. Lovers of simplicity pay us homage in this sense; frustration is the mark of the latter while the former boast of their comforts.
Sustained on the fruit of their own ways, the fruit born of critical human examination burns as it disagrees in the stomach. Devices, which always succeed in reducing the world into manageable parts, neatly dice and cube our flesh with precise edges. As a function of something's or someone's utility, humanity can only be as human as hierarchically stacked flesh. Those that inherit their thoughts and methods, never to consider them beyond the promise to yeild certain results, end up disfiguring the best of all possible contributions to our world when they choose quick understanding over the more painful and careful pursuits of self examination.
When the quicker becomes the better, satisfaction is planned around and through the inconvieniances that other people offer, and a deep knowledge of ourselves suddenly seems mysterious if not completely irrelevant to how we've decided a life should be constructed. Soon, we will not recognize ourselves because we will no longer seek the window to knowledge in another's eyes where the truest and most painful of our reflections wait.

Rough Notes for Framing a Discussion of FEAR

Thinking that I may have flogged the point of certain aspects of Vulnerability, and wholly ignored some other of its functions....I want to go into what it is that Fearis.....and from some general thoughts, see some interplay and relationship with the value of Vulnerability.

rough notes and ideas:
...the grand utility of forming the will, against all prejudice and fear, for the purpose of understanding our fellow human being is that we may gain access to ourselves through another even when the condition exists that we are both blind to particulars within ourselves.

The unknown is dark, and so we prefer to play in the light of those things we think we know. Fear is the dark; a mechanism within acting to scare us away from that place we "know not what." It is the boundary of our current identity, whatever that may be per individual. We prefer to play in the safety of light; as the oldest children in the Universe, we still do not see how Fear may contain an autonomous belief-structure of its own.

Compelling us always to action for self-preservation, Fear pervades even within the most willful constructs and about even the strongest ideas we can make of ourselves. The words "Honor," "Hypocrisy," "Heros" and "Hurt" are all made per generation and are kept relevant only as long as certain fears preserve the boundaries of a greater awareness. Can we now preserve against Fear, with awarenesses of it, to seek access to an ever-evolving progress within this human project? Do we dare share ourselves at this depth, to become filthy in another's truths and to have this become our common religion? It shows that we are still not ready for this evolution: "Life is comfortable, yes, but it could be more so . . ." " . . . " " ." And our technologies tell us that we are much too smart and advanced for need to wish upon ourselves a daily migration into a better education of the individual and her natural circumstance. So, either we will see ourselves in scale with the cosmos and invite that new religion, or we will go on imbued with cravings for safety and comfort-- synonymous with a craving for Fear-- staying swathed in illusions as children while thinking of ourselves as having already broken into a great status.

Thursday, May 6, 2010

General Reflections on Emotional Responses to Idea Exchange (III)

::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: General Refl’s . . .(III)

There is a class of conversations marked by single, and multiple, individual's(s') eagerness to listen and a genuine expectation to attempt as direct a mental connection as is possible, so as to glean the maximum from following not just the words spoken but the pauses and emphases and paths of thought of another. To open one’s self to the style of cognition, and the actual mental path and processes of another, is to invite the study of how another thinks as just as intellectually valuable—if not more so in some cases—as what can be found agreeable or objectionable in what is actually being said. The other individual, being the genuine subject of this study/process, becomes wholly loved in advance. It is very strange to understand and communicate this. I can say it no better than that, though I will try . . . In advance of knowing anything at all about them; as if anything that could already be attached to an idea of them is suspended from that present moment—They are loved without attributes.

This has to happen; just like when true love is present in a romantic relationship it is necessarily the case that both persons are made vulnerable enough so each has the ability to hurt the other. Vulnerability lets another in, and I do not think there is any true/real love where there is no vulnerability. And even further: To the degree that there exists vulnerability, there also exists some portion of genuine love. So I will extrapolate . . . To whatever quality and degree we are engaging in idea exchange with another, there is present some proportional quality and degree of vulnerability and consequentially some degree of genuine love. Our ultimate goal then, when we truly desire the freest flow of idea exchange—and are not deceiving ourselves with the want to satisfy some other psychological preoccupation—Our ultimate goal in the freest flow of idea-exchange should be complete and transparent vulnerability.

The value and emergence of this, as a practical reality, I can probably best explain in an example of how I experienced it and became aware of its truth and power as a concept and as an active tool to be continuously called upon and triggered . . . I will leave out the nuanced particulars of the story to emphasize that it is not these things that are most important, as it is the paths of thought which have produced the point.

I was having a conversation in a group that contained a good friend of mine, with whom idea exchange had been fluid from day one. Though his girlfriend and I, from the second we met, had in-between us some inexplicable intellectual tension that frustrated our attempts to communicate so badly that it eventually relegated our communication to making her boyfriend our proxy. Never had I experienced such a phenomenon, especially in another who seemed to highly value human interaction and conversation. (It is probably accurate that, at this point, I had something of the notion in my head that it was my fault and that I could fix the communication barrier by trying harder, and if this didn’t work that the problem was in her head and/or effort.) So on this particular day, the conversation had flowed so that the others in the group had pursued an offshoot of the original topic (on the nature and barriers of language, ironically) so that both she and I had recognized each other’s voices as the only ones still wanting to pull on the main thread. We settled on each other’s eyes cautiously; we were pushed through a pre-existing emotion, no doubt containing bundles of assumptions about the other, because now we shared the same want.

I already knew what she wanted to explain to me. She wanted to impress upon me how amazing it was that a particular character, both word and picture, in [A specific tribal LANGUAGE] was used to represent [a specific, transcendent MEANING by virtue of its symbol and understanding as a composite]. What I needed her to understand was that the meaning of the character is limited [to its cultural context of MEANING]. I was interjecting “yes” after “sure” to gain my break (by also passively wanting to feign support for her idea) so I could ground her illogical, wandering, liberal, mystical and fantastical predilections in sound lo—Until she broke herself –midsentence-- on whatever it was in the nagging expressions of my half-hearted will about which she, too, must have attached a growing distaste. And then she willfully subjected herself to me. Everything about her tone and demeanor tuned in on me, and in the sharpest halt, a barely perceptible pivot, she had made herself genuinely vulnerable and transparent in front of me. She said: “I want you to teach me how you think.” As soon as she said this I felt disarmed of mental barriers I never knew I was building and using against her. I felt an immediate, direct and impossible connection to her that shook me so much from where my mind had been looking that that all I could see now was my own ignorance in overlooking the magnitude and scope of her point. . . .FULL MEANING. Her vulnerability—instantly and sincerely inviting me to impress my ignorance upon her—literally carried the opposite effect. I was let in to her, by her submitting to me. This happened quickly, and I had to recognize and act on the invitation (which I did purely with trust in what was created in me emotionally by my recognition of a love advanced to me out of a suspension of all that may have brought to characterize me before this moment). I could not speak but to say “Oh my god.” I finally explained myself to her, and came away with this valuable notion of the operations of vulnerability: I had to be vulnerable so I could walk on her words, as there were no pathways there yet in my own head.

I think this gets at it a bit. I also want to go into emotional responses to idea exchange that are characterized by other pre-conditions and lead to myriad impasses . . . I also want to tie/compare/contrast this notion of emotion, vulnerability and love in idea exchange to Socrates’ bringing of someone to a state of APORIA by exasperating them through definition and an endless regression of refutation. And in a later post, I want to show the communal function of this concept as I see it’s uses easily confounded to support, and “inform,” zeitgeist societal paradigms (macro), specifically responding to how I understand Dr. Marina Berzins McCoy to approach the term. Catharsis by surrogate will be of special interest here.

Also, I think this story and the function of vulnerability would be interesting if discussed within Aristotle's conception of reciprocation in friendship; again, not presupposing the value of the polis over the individual-- but going on a journey to detect whatever community would naturally precipitate from knowing an individual (and group of individuals) vulnerably, specifically and transparently.

but I’ll end here with these thoughts for now....

Thoughts anyone?

Wednesday, May 5, 2010

A New Preamble

I propose this as a new Preamble of a society which seeks to found itself on pursuing only activities and thoughts and sciences concerned with the discovery of what it means to be a human being strapped to a rock, by some force we know not what but call gravity, floating in some thing/place we call the cosmos. Such a society would be founded with the revelation that knowing who and what we are inextricably precedes and informs action and also, therefore, any and all normative systems formed from such action. Such a society would be diametrically opposed to any other society whose precepts or latent, devolving philosophies allow for the valuation of resources so that they may be used as luxuries or accumulated into wealth.

A New Preamble

When, in the course of the culmination of knowledge concerning the human condition, it becomes necessary to dissolve all extant paradigms within the greater pool of identity-- all resources pulled from this Earth may be seen as best used for the augmentation of this identity-- a New Marker in history will be achieved. As Reason within individuals is compelled to see itself in scale with the 'Cosmos,' the borders of its paradigm will consequentially expand, in scale, with this new identity. As a widespread revelation, this will cause the current indoctrination to particular facts to no longer satisfy as the popular definition of the word: education. As it has been the case throughout human evolution, the rise of particular changes in the genome have made others non-competitive for sexual reproduction. Should our species make it far enough into the future, such changes will dictate our evolution over and over again; Especially as a new trait, our cognitive evolution should not be seen as exempt from this selection, irrespective of any illusion of certainty we now feel or have ever felt.

If you have ever wondered: "Is this person truly giving to me what they think is most important in life?"

It can only be that every person is giving what they think is most important in life at all times-- we practice these things as only we can see them, and we adopt these models as wishes plucked from a cognitive web of memories. We can only draw from our predilections, those things in life that tug on our heart; we dare not betray that love lest we betray and lose ourselves. If it is most important that a person hide from themselves, that they not wrestle with truths, they will show you the tools they use to stay hidden: lies, distractions, truncated listening, quick/easy responses, those things they practice most. We cannot help but to always be practicing something. If we stay unknown to ourselves, sustained by a fear of exploration into those things we do not know and of those questions that we are unwilling to ask of ourselves and others and of our natural world, then we have shrunk our greatest of contributions and have made the perimeter of our identity to be ever-guarded by the fears we inherit. Here we will hide in Fear, and what should be a knowledge that we may be lost, will only feel like a disorientating headache. You cannot know what you have not explored; you may only be informed, or overwhelmed, by receiving deep and mysterious signals from your own biology when its senses the crux of a disconnect within. It seems as though the brain wants to know itself . . . with or without help from its host. And, hidden away inside ourselves, the great tragedy- to some, and great educator to others- is that we are able to hide nothing. We cannot avoid giving those things we have taken from life, as only this life can fill human stores. We can all see each other, but what we can see determines what we can take from another. Nothing is hidden in this world exuding energy except for those things opaque in our own heads. The definition of the micro paradigm is exactly what individuals do and do not allow themselves to see: what ethics stand in the way of a person acting freely, exploring freely, questioning absolutely free. What kind of inheritances are these ethical limits in any and a l l forms in which they arrive? I spare none to any practice, system, cult, philosophy, religion, business model, government, friend or family. But what we currently find ourselves giving another is indeed what we hold most dear. We are what we love. What we love is what we practice most. What we practice is all we have to give another.

"A person will worship something, have no doubt about that. We may think our tribute is paid in secret in the dark recesses of our hearts, but it will out. That which dominates our imaginations and our thoughts will determine our lives, and our character. Therefore, it behooves us to be careful what we worship, for what we are worshipping we are becoming." -RWE

Tuesday, May 4, 2010

Vulnerability and Nietzsche

Essentially, the recognition of one’s own vulnerability in the face of a hostile, natural world allows the individual to access themselves deeply and internally where the expression of power is an act which allows the individual to valuate themselves with the external result. Even though Nietzsche claims that the autonomous, aristocratic and supremely powerful individual values themselves in relation to nothing outside their own action, it is necessary that they are still looking only into the external world to see the result of their action for their appraisal of value in themselves. There is an inward, vulnerable nature of the human which loving only the external products of physical action grossly and dangerously ignores. The path to understanding one’s own inward vulnerabilities, and the value of this knowledge, precipitates into a community of individuals who know what is best for each other because they deeply and personally know each other and themselves. Typically, we see our own manifestations of strength played out in our own lives and communities where the human being has the choice to take on, or not, the education of being informed by the objects of their own external valuation which can lead into an awareness of the value of another’s, and their own, vulnerability.

In primitive mental youth, we love the physical as its own end and chase it with all the strength we have. There is much joy and happiness in this the success of this, as Nietzsche indicates, but once you have loved enough physical things for their physical ends, the saturation of physical love begins to feel mundane. This mundane feeling does not satisfy our perennial longing to love and so we are shaken free, by lack of satisfaction in the diminishing marginal utility of entertainment with manifestations of the physical. Our longing causes us to search within the numerous objects of our physical love to discover what it is that we are still missing. We still long because it is in our internal nature that we feel our vulnerability crying out to reach that of another’s. We discover that all the varieties of objects and bodies and the strength we exerted to obtain them had the ability to be accessed and loved simply because they possessed a common vulnerability; All things can be understood and accessed by the natural condition of their existence with a vulnerable nature. The revelation of this fundamental commonality gives birth to a desire to see all things with existence reach their maximized expression of existence. At this point our intellect seeks to believe in, and experiment with, ideas that we think will better all things that exist. To bringing these thoughts in meaningful contact with things that exist necessarily requires a preoccupation with the function of corresponding action and “ought” claims, or laws. A preoccupation with the proper role of action and law to better all things in existence eventually makes the individual want to allow for themselves an education with an unlimited scope. Different approaches and styles and values concerning knowledge and human understanding are explored, desired and loved. A society where only force is respected because of its external results cannot sustain a society at all because it only incorporates half of human nature. The potential society of individuals, which go through the process I describe above, is not characterized by an individual’s selfish state of bliss for the satisfaction of themselves. It is the experiential truth that somehow the individual’s personal, selfish interest is transformed—and forever marked—by being encompassing of the whole of existence for the sake of a better, specific and more transparent experience with the individual. This is the process that cannot help but to emerge to shape our society once Nietzsche’s credible critique of modern morality is blended with the proper and more full understanding of our nature as also containing vulnerability.